I failed to see that the tools could not be entirely without
context, as they were tools in my use. As
a software, the tools have processes that work behind the scenes to pull
information from its database. The creator
of the tool decides how the information will be presented or how the data will
be organized. The creator also decides
which versions of texts to pull from.
He/she also determines where in the text the tool will pull information
from and what constitutes a searchable term (i.e. does the tool search for
plurals? For both capitalized and lower
case versions of a word?). I cannot
control those things (which incidentally are the elements of the tools that
left me feeling decontextualized), but I control what kind of data is pulled. I control the key word the text searches
for. As the user or operator, I control whether
the text pulls 5 or 500 words with the key word. I decided that the Alex collocation should
pull all instances of the word “Language” in Vindication of the Rights of Women.
That control alone provides some context in the sense that my actions
have context within the course. The text
has meaning for the course, as does the term, therefore the data pulled by the
collocation has context. That data may
be removed from the context of the text itself, but that does not mean that it
is entirely without context. In other
words, the tools cannot be entirely without context because I am not entirely
without context. This thinking, which
led to a productive idea about the relationship between the operator and the
tool (productive in the sense that it holds repercussions for the exploratory
and more dramatically for my work in other courses), happened when I shed an
unproductive binary that had resulted in hours of misery in the days before.
What I am really touching on here, I think, leads to a
discussion about epistemology. The
online tools that we used can be seen as a kind of database reading. With enough information across enough texts
we can potentially make claims about larger conceptual concerns across texts
and historical periods. In this
exploratory, of course, we had neither enough texts nor enough time to make
those kinds of considerations. Even
still, it could be that these kinds of tools - or, rather, the ways that we use
them - represent an epistemology or a way of knowing about texts and about
validating what we know about textual analysis. (The rest of you may, of course, have already
figured this out, and, if that is the case, I apologize for repeating it here,
but I failed to see this in my first attempts at using the tools, so I feel the
need to discuss it here now.) I do not
mean, of course, that the individual tools used for this exploratory represent
an epistemology; they have too many limitations for that. I would, however, argue that their potential
represents an epistemology. Epistemology
is, of course, a theory of knowledge and of the nature of knowledge. As discussed in our rhet/comp digital culture
course this week, databases, and potentially collocations, represent an
alternative to close reading in which claims are made based on the presence of
information across multiple texts. If we
had a full survey of Enlightenment texts about rhetoric, for example, we might
use the collocation to make the claim that the term eloquence comes to mean
rhetoric during this period. Granted, it
would take a much more sophisticated collocation than Alex or the Internet
Archive to accomplish something like this, but it may be possible.
To my mind, this form of analysis via database is a way of knowing, a system that produces knowledge. With the right amount of data, it would be possible to create knowledge about texts. (I have a few issues with this in terms of how such claims possible without reading texts and seeing information in context, but I will admit that doing so is possible). In addition, in explaining exactly how the databases are developed and programmed, this epistemology interrogates how it creates knowledge. There are, admittedly, limitations to collocations and other online tools, but there are limitations to the systems of Aristotle, Erasmus, Perelman, and Campbell as well, limitations that we have spent the last five week discussing and that all lead back to context.
To my mind, this form of analysis via database is a way of knowing, a system that produces knowledge. With the right amount of data, it would be possible to create knowledge about texts. (I have a few issues with this in terms of how such claims possible without reading texts and seeing information in context, but I will admit that doing so is possible). In addition, in explaining exactly how the databases are developed and programmed, this epistemology interrogates how it creates knowledge. There are, admittedly, limitations to collocations and other online tools, but there are limitations to the systems of Aristotle, Erasmus, Perelman, and Campbell as well, limitations that we have spent the last five week discussing and that all lead back to context.
At the end of our last class period, Dr. Graban made a
comment that links epistemology and context.
She stated – roughly – that Aristotle’s system of rhetoric served to
reinforce an oppressive social understanding of "polis". Her comment helps to place Aristotle in a specific context, a context
that illustrates the assumptions underlying his epistemological system and that
has bearing on the knowledge created through that system. Do we discount or consider unsophisticated
some of the knowledge created through Aristotle’s system because of that
oppressive context? Do we posit, for
example, that what we can create with his commonplaces is limited because of
the way they perpetuate his context? I
ask this question because many of the other theorists that we have read in this
strand – Erasmus, Perelman, Bacon, Campbell – all cover similar ground to
Aristotle. They all treat on similar
themes; they all reorganize and reclassify rhetorical systems in the face of a
changing context. I guess what I am
after here – and I realize that it is a bit half baked at this point – is
whether or not a shifting context can invalidate the knowledge created by an
episteme and create the need for a new one.
In the case of this week’s exploratory, the context in which we worked –
in terms of the course context and the limitations of the online tools – meant
that the knowledge created from the database episteme was not valid or at least
highly questionable. Can the same be
said for the larger epistemic systems that we have studied this semester?
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.